Courses:

Foundations of Cognition >> Content Detail



Study Materials



Readings

 
The readings listed below are the foundation of this course. Where available, journal article abstracts from PubMed (an online database providing access to citations from biomedical literature) are included.

Debate

Well, does language shape thought or what?

History of Cognitive Science

Freud, S. "Formulations Regarding The Two Principles in Mental Functioning." 1911. In The Freud Reader. Edited by P. Gay. New York: Norton, 1989, pp. 301-306.

Gardner, H. The Mind's New Science. Basic Books, 1985, pp. 3-7.

Lorenz, K. On Agression. New York: Bantam Books, 1966, pp. 183-188, and 210-211.

Nilsson, D-E., and S. Pelger. "A Pessimistic Estimate of The Time Required for An Eye To Evolve." 1994. Reprinted in Evolution. Edited by M. Ridley. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997, pp. 293-301.

Plato. Meno. Excerpt (79e - 86d).

Tolman, E. C. "Cognitive Maps in Rats and Men." Psychological Review 55(4) (1948): 189-208.

Watson, J. B. Behaviorism: The Modern Note in Psychology.

Big Debates in Cognitive Science

Dennett, D. "The Logical Geography of Computational Approaches to the Cognitive Sciences." In Brainstorms.

Pinker, S. "The Rules of Language." Science 253(5019) (Aug 2, 1991): 530-5.

PubMed abstract:  Language and cognition have been explained as the products of a homogeneous associative memory structure or alternatively, of a set of genetically determined computational modules in which rules manipulate symbolic representations. Intensive study of one phenomenon of English grammar and how it is processed and acquired suggest that both theories are partly right. Regular verbs (walk-walked) are computed by a suffixation rule in a neural system for grammatical processing; irregular verbs (run-ran) are retrieved from an associative memory.

Rumelhart, D. E., and J. L. McClelland. "On Learning The Past Tenses of English Verbs." In McClelland & Rumelhart. 1986. (Optional)

Cognitive Architectures

Anderson, J. R., and L. J. Schooler. "Reflections of the Environment in Memory." Psychological Science 2 (1991): 396-408.

Chater, N., and M. Oaksford. "Ten Years of the Rational Analysis of Cognition." Trends in Cognitive Science 3, 57-65.

PubMed abstract:  Rational analysis is an empirical program that attempts to explain the function and purpose of cognitive processes. This article looks back on a decade of research outlining the rational analysis methodology and how the approach relates to other work in cognitive science. We illustrate rational analysis by considering how it has been applied to memory and reasoning. From the perspective of traditional cognitive science, the cognitive system can appear to be a rather arbitrary assortment of mechanisms with equally arbitrary limitations. In contrast, rational analysis views cognition as intricately adapted to its environment and to the problems it faces.

Collins, A. M., and M. R. Quillian. "Retrieval Time from Semantic Memory." Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 8 (1969): 240-247. Reprinted in Computation and Intelligence. Edited by G. F. Luger. Menlo Park, CA: AAAI Press, pp. 191-201.

McClelland, J. L. "Connectionist Models of Memory." In The Oxford Handbook of Memory. Edited by E. Tulving and F. I. M. Craik. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000, pp. 583-596.

Recitation Marr's Levels

Marr, D. Chap. 1 in Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Information. San Francisco: Freeman.

Recitation East Coast vs. West Coast

Fodor, J., and Z. Pylyshyn. "Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture." Cognition 28 (1988): 3-71. (Optional)

Newell. Unified Theories of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990, pp. 17-36. (Optional) (Symbolic Models)

Pinker. How the Mind Works. New York: W. W. Norton & Company. 1997, pp. 69-77. (Optional) (Symbolic Models)

Recitation Domain Specificity vs Domain Generality

Fodor, J. The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 1983, pp. 1-38, and 47-52. (Excerpt)

———. Acknowledgements and Chaps. 4, and 5 in The Mind Doesn't Work That Way. Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 2000.

Frensch, P. A., and A. Buchner. "Domain-generality Versus Domain Specificity." In The Nature of Cognition. Edited by R. J. Sternberg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999, pp. 155-163.

Pinker, S. The Language Instinct. New York: William and Morrow Co., 1994, pp. 419-430. (Excerpt)

Mental Representation I

Goldstone, R. L., and A. Kersten. "Concepts and Categories." In Comprehensive Handbook of Psychology: Experimental Psychology. Edited by A. F. Healy, and R. W. Proctor. Vol. 4. New York: Wiley. (in press)

Medin, and Murphy. "The Role of Theories in Conceptual Coherence." Chap. 19 in Concepts: Core Readings. Edited by E. Margulis, and S. Laurence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999.

Wittgenstein. "Philosophical Investigations." Chap. 6 in Concepts: Core Readings. Edited by E. Margulis, and S. Laurence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999. (Excerpt)

Mental Representation II

Barsalou, Lawrence W. "Perceptual Symbol Systems. " In Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 22, 4, pp. 577-660.

PubMed abstract:  Prior to the twentieth century, theories of knowledge were inherently perceptual. Since then, developments in logic, statistics, and programming languages have inspired amodal theories that rest on principles fundamentally different from those underlying perception. In addition, perceptual approaches have become widely viewed as untenable because they are assumed to implement recording systems, not conceptual systems. A perceptual theory of knowledge is developed here in the context of current cognitive science and neuroscience. During perceptual experience, association areas in the brain capture bottom-up patterns of activation in sensory-motor areas. Later, in a top-down manner, association areas partially reactivate sensory-motor areas to implement perceptual symbols. The storage and reactivation of perceptual symbols operates at the level of perceptual components--not at the level of holistic perceptual experiences. Through the use of selective attention, schematic representations of perceptual components are extracted from experience and stored in memory (e.g., individual memories of green, purr, hot). As memories of the same component become organized around a common frame, they implement a simulator that produces limitless simulations of the component (e.g., simulations of purr). Not only do such simulators develop for aspects of sensory experience, they also develop for aspects of proprioception (e.g., lift, run) and introspection (e.g., compare, memory, happy, hungry). Once established, these simulators implement a basic conceptual system that represents types, supports categorization, and produces categorical inferences. These simulators further support productivity, propositions, and abstract concepts, thereby implementing a fully functional conceptual system. Productivity results from integrating simulators combinatorially and recursively to produce complex simulations. Propositions result from binding simulators to perceived individuals to represent type-token relations. Abstract concepts are grounded in complex simulations of combined physical and introspective events. Thus, a perceptual theory of knowledge can implement a fully functional conceptual system while avoiding problems associated with amodal symbol systems. Implications for cognition, neuroscience, evolution, development, and artificial intelligence are explored.

Lakoff, G., and M. Johnson. "The Metaphorical Structure of the Human Conceptual System." Cognitive-Science 4(2) (1980): 195-208.

Landauer, T. K., and S. T. Dumais. "A Solution to Plato's Problem: The Latent Semantic Analysis Theory of the Acquisition, Induction, and Representation of Knowledge." Psychological Review 104 (1997).

Potter, M. C. "Understanding Sentences and Scenes: The Role of Conceptual Short Term Memory." In Fleeting Memories. Edited by V. Coltheart. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1999.

DEBATE on Mental Imagery

Kosslyn, S. "Mental Imagery." In Visual Cognition: An Invitation to Cognitive Science. Edited by D. N. Osherson, and S. M. Kosslyn. Vol. 2. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995, pp. 267-295.

Pylyshyn. Mental Imagery: In Search of a Theory. BBS. (in press)

Analogy & Similarity

Gentner, D., and A. B. Markman. "Structure Mapping in Analogy and Similarity." In Mind Readings. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1998, pp. 127-156.

Goodman, N. "Seven Strictures on Similarity." In Problems and Projects. New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1972, pp. 437-447.

Medin, D. L., R. Goldstone, and D. Gentner. "Respects for Similarity." Psychological Review 100 (1993): 254-278.

Shepard, R. N. "Multidimensional Scaling, Clustering, and Treefitting." Science 210 (1980): 390-398. (Optional)

Tversky, A. "Features of Similarity." Psychological Review 84 (1977): 327-352.

Cognitive Development

Murphy. G. Chaps. 9 and 10 in The Big Book of Concepts.

Generalization & Similarity

Mill, J. S. A System of Logic. 1843. Excerpt. (Optional)

Shepard, R. N. "Multidimensional Scaling, Clustering, and Tree-Fitting." Science 210 (1980): 390-398. (Optional--just refresh your memory from Lera's lecture)

———. "Towards a Universal Theory of Generalization for Psychological Science." Science 237 (1987): 1317-1323.

PubMed abstract:  A psychological space is established for any set of stimuli by determining metric distances between the stimuli such that the probability that a response learned to any stimulus will generalize to any other is an invariant monotonic function of the distance between them. To a good approximation, this probability of generalization (i) decays exponentially with this distance, and (ii) does so in accordance with one of two metrics, depending on the relation between the dimensions along which the stimuli vary. These empirical regularities are mathematically derivable from universal principles of natural kinds and probabilistic geometry that may, through evolutionary internalization, tend to govern the behaviors of all sentient organisms.

Tenenbaum, J. B., and T. L. Griffiths. "Generalization, Similarity, and Bayesian Inference." Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24(4) (2001).

PubMed abstract:  Shepard has argued that a universal law should govern generalization across different domains of perception and cognition, as well as across organisms from different species or even different planets. Starting with some basic assumptions about natural kinds, he derived an exponential decay function as the form of the universal generalization gradient, which accords strikingly well with a wide range of empirical data. However, his original formulation applied only to the ideal case of generalization from a single encountered stimulus to a single novel stimulus, and for stimuli that can be represented as points in a continuous metric psychological space. Here we recast Shepard's theory in a more general Bayesian framework and show how this naturally extends his approach to the more realistic situation of generalizing from multiple consequential stimuli with arbitrary representational structure. Our framework also subsumes a version of Tversky's set-theoretic model of similarity, which is conventionally thought of as the primary alternative to Shepard's continuous metric space model of similarity and generalization. This unification allows us not only to draw deep parallels between the set-theoretic and spatial approaches, but also to significantly advance the explanatory power of set-theoretic models

Tversky, A. "Features of Similarity." Psychological Review 84 (1977): 327-352.

(Optional -- just refresh your memory from Lera's lecture)

Association & Categorization

Gluck, M., and G. Bower. "From Conditioning to Category Learning: An Adaptive Network Model." Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 8 (1988): 37-50.

PubMed abstract:  We used adaptive network theory to extend the Rescorla-Wagner (1972) least mean squares (LMS) model of associative learning to phenomena of human learning and judgment. In three experiments subjects learned to categorize hypothetical patients with particular symptom patterns as having certain diseases. When one disease is far more likely than another, the model predicts that subjects will substantially overestimate the diagnosticity of the more valid symptom for the rare disease. The results of Experiments 1 and 2 provide clear support for this prediction in contradistinction to predictions from probability matching, exemplar retrieval, or simple prototype learning models. Experiment 3 contrasted the adaptive network model with one predicting pattern-probability matching when patients always had four symptoms (chosen from four opponent pairs) rather than the presence or absence of each of four symptoms, as in Experiment 1. The results again support the Rescorla-Wagner LMS learning rule as embedded within an adaptive network model.

Hume, D. A Treatise of Human Nature. Part I Section 4 (pp. 10-13), Part III Section VI (pp. 86-94), Part III Section XII (pp. 130-143.) (Optional)

Kruschke, J. K. "Human Category Learning: Implications for Back Propagation Models." Connection Science 5 (1) (1993): 3-37.

Nosofsky, R. M. "Optimal Performance and Exemplar Models of Classification." In Rational Models of Cognition. Edited by M. Oaksford, and N. Chater. New York: Oxford University Press, 1998, pp. 219-247.

OR

Smith, E. E., and D. L. Medin. "The Exemplar View." In Categories and Concepts. Harvard. 1981.

Tenenbaum, J. B. "Rules and Similarity in Concept Learning." In Advances in Neural Information Processing Systems 12. 2000.

DISCUSSION on Problems of Induction

Goodman, N. "The New Riddle of Induction." Chap. 3 in Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1955.

Murphy, G. L. "Taxonomic Organization and the Basic Level of Concepts." Chap. 7 in The Big Book of Concepts. MIT Press, 2002.

OR

Rosch, E. "Principles of Categorization." In Cognition and Categorization. Edited by E. Rosch, and B. Lloyd. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1978. (Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings. Edited by E. Margulis, and S. Laurence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999, pp. 189-206.)

Osherson, D. N., E. E. Smith, O. Wilkie, A. Lopez, and E. Shafir. "Category-Based Induction." Psychological Review 97 (1990): 185-200.

Sanjana, N., and J. B. Tenenbaum. "Bayesian Models of Inductive Generalization." In Advances in Neural Information Processing Systems 15. 2002.

Causality

Glymour, C. "Learning Causes: Psychological Explanations of Causal Explanation." Minds and Machines 8 (1998): 39-60.

Hewstone, M. Causal Attribution: From Cognitive Processes to Collective Beliefs. Blackwell. Excerpt.

Scholl, B. J., and P. Tremoulet. "Perceptual Causality and Animacy." Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4(8) (2000): 299-309.

PubMed abstract:  Certain simple visual displays consisting of moving 2-D geometric shapes can give rise to percepts with high-level properties such as causality and animacy. This article reviews recent research on such phenomena, which began with the classic work of Michotte and of Heider and Simmel. The importance of such phenomena stems in part from the fact that these interpretations seem to be largely perceptual in nature - to be fairly fast, automatic, irresistible and highly stimulus driven - despite the fact that they involve impressions typically associated with higher-level cognitive processing. This research suggests that just as the visual system works to recover the physical structure of the world by inferring properties such as 3-D shape, so too does it work to recover the causal and social structure of the world by inferring properties such as causality and animacy.

Shanks, D. R. "Is Human Learning Rational?" The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 48A (2) (1995): 257-279.

PubMed abstract:  We can predict and control events in the world via associative learning. Such learning is rational if we come to believe that an associative relationship exists between a pair of events only when it truly does. The statistical metric delta P, the difference between the probability of an outcome event in the presence of the predictor and its probability in the absence of the predictor tells us when and to what extent events are indeed related. Contrary to what is often claimed, humans' associative judgements compare very favourably with the delta P metric, even in situations where multiple predictive cues are in competition for association with the outcome. How do humans achieve this judgmental accuracy? I argue that it is not via the application of an explicit mental version of the delta P rule. Instead, accurate judgements are an emergent property of an associationist learning process of the sort that has become common in adaptive network models of cognition. Such an associationist mechanism is the "means" to a normative or statistical "end".

Intuitive Theories

Carey, S. (1985). Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings. Edited by Margolis, and Laurence. MIT Press.

Goldman, A., and V. Gallese. "Mirror Neurons and the Simulation Theory of Mind-Reading." Trends in Cognitive Science 2 (12) (1998): 493-501.

Gopnik, A., and C. Glymour. "Causal Maps and Bayes Nets: A Cognitive and Computational Account of Theory-Formation." In The Cognitive Basis of Science. Edited by Carruthers et al. Cambridge, 2002.

Tenenbaum, J. B., and S. Niyogi. Learning Abstract Causal Knowledge.

DISCUSSION on Rationality & Symbolic Reasoning

Ahn, W-K., and L. M. Graham. "The Impact of Necessity and Sufficiency in the Wason Four-Card Selection Task." Psychological Science 10 (1999): 237-242.

Cheng, P. W., and K. J. Holyoak. "On the Natural Selection of Reasoning Theories." Cognition 33 (1989): 285-313.

Cosmides, L., and J. Tooby. "Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange." In The Adapted Mind. Edited by J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, and J. Tooby. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989, pp. 163-228.

Oaksford M., and N. Chater, "A Rational Analysis of the Selection Task As Optimal Data Selection." Psychological Review 101 (1994): 608-631.

Probabilistic Reasoning

Chase, V. M., R. Hertwig, and G. Gigerenzer. "Visions of Rationality." Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2 (1998): 206-214.

Nisbett, R. E., D. H. Krantz, C. Jepson, and Z. Kunda. "The Use of Statistical Heuristics in Everyday Inductive Reasoning." Psychological Review 90 (1983): 339-363.

Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. "Probabilistic Reasoning." (1974/1983). In Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Edited by A. Goldman, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993, pp. 45-68.

Decision Making

Shafir, E., and A. Tversky. "Decision Making." In Thinking: An Invitation to Cognitive Science. Edited by E. E. Smith, and D. N. Osherson. Vol. 2. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995, pp. 77-100.

Stephens, D. W., and J. R. Krebs. "Risk-Sensitive Foraging." Chap. 6 in Foraging Theory. Princeton University Press, 1986.

DISCUSSION on Frontiers of Cognition

Frank, R. H. Passions Within Reason: The Strategic Role of the Emotions. New York: Norton, 1988, pp. 1-14, 19-35, 43-63, and 185-211.

Greene, J., and J. Haidt. "How (and Where) Does Moral Judgment Work?" Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6, 12 (1 Dec 2002): 517-523.

PubMed abstract:  Moral psychology has long focused on reasoning, but recent evidence suggests that moral judgment is more a matter of emotion and affective intuition than deliberate reasoning. Here we discuss recent findings in psychology and cognitive neuroscience, including several studies that specifically investigate moral judgment. These findings indicate the importance of affect, although they allow that reasoning can play a restricted but significant role in moral judgment. They also point towards a preliminary account of the functional neuroanatomy of moral judgment, according to which many brain areas make important contributions to moral judgment although none is devoted specifically to it.

Miller, G. F., and P. M. Todd. "Mate Choice Turns Cognitive." Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2 (1998): 190-198.

Searle, J. "How to Study Consciousness Scientifically." Brain Research Reviews 26 (1998): 379-387.

PubMed abstract:  The neurosciences have advanced to the point that we can now treat consciousness as a scientific problem like any other. The problem is to explain how brain processes cause consciousness and how consciousness is realized in the brain. Progress is impeded by a number of philosophical mistakes, and the aim of this paper is to remove nine of those mistakes: (i) consciousness cannot be defined; (ii) consciousness is subjective but science is objective; (iii) brain processes cannot explain consciousness; (iv) the problem of 'qualia' should be set aside; (v) consciousness is epiphenomenal; (vi) consciousness has no evolutionary function; (vii) a causal account of consciousness is necessarily dualistic; (viii) science is reductionistic, so a scientific account of consciousness would show it reducible to something else; and (ix) an account of consciousness must be an information processing account.

Memory Systems I

Language & Thought

Boroditsky, Lera. "Linguistic Relativity." In Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. 2003.

Bowerman, M., and S. Choi. "Shaping Meanings for Language: Universal and Language-Specific in the Acquisition of Spatial Semantic Categories." In Language Acquisition and Conceptual Development. Edited by M. Bowerman, and S. Levinson. 2001, pp. 215-256.

Pullum, Geoffrey K. "The Great Eskimo Vocabulary Hoax." In The Great Eskimo Vocabulary Hoax, and Other Irreverent Essays On The Study of Language. University of Chicago Press, 1991, pp. 159-171.

Slobin, D. "From "thought and language'' to "thinking for speaking''." In Rethinking Linguistic Relativity. Edited by J. J. Gumperz, and S. C. Levinson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.



 



 








© 2009-2020 HigherEdSpace.com, All Rights Reserved.
Higher Ed Space ® is a registered trademark of AmeriCareers LLC.